Dialogue & Ethical Decision Making in a Pluralistic Society (Part 1)

Tom-of-the-coast-of-Maine-2This is the first of two essays on the issues related to ethical debate and decision making in a pluralist society.  This first essay examines how language and issues of defining what is real and what is not present unique problems.   The second essay examines John Rawl’s A Theory of Justice as offering one approach to dealing with the problems of pluralism described in this first essay.

There are a great many advantages to living in a country like the U.S. where we are ostensibly free to believe what we choose to believe and free to express those beliefs with only very modest restrictions.  Freedom of speech opens the door to dialogue between persons of  both similar and differing points of view.  We can discuss important matters as a society in an open manner and use the representative democratic process to regulate our society as a nation of laws.  In addition to being a nation that enjoys freedom of speech, we are also a very diverse nation made up of people from a large number to cultures, religious traditions, countries, political persuasions, educational backgrounds and an increasing number of  languages.  

In this sense, we are a pluralist nation.  In the US there is no official, national or established church as  in the United Kingdom or Spain.  There are a variety of political factions and conceptions of how a people should be governed (or govern themselves).  There are real political differences vying for public attention unlike in countries like the Peoples’ Republic of China or Myanmar where political disagreement and challenges to the government are suppressed, sometimes violently.  Issues are debated by politicians, in the press,  among individuals and interest groups.  Laws and regulations are challenged in courts. Arguments are made and judgments rendered. Our religions traditions range from Christian, Jewish, Islamic, Buddhist  Hindu, Naturist, Agnostic to Atheist.  There is no prescribed set of beliefs about the nature of humankind or the cosmos itself.  There are many views, some more powerful than others, but all are officially not only tolerated but also (with the exception of the most vile) generally welcomed.

In the main, this pluralism, to the extent that there is real sharing between and openness to  differing groups, enriches our society, expands the horizons of those who participate in that sharing and leads to a greater national solidarity and sense of purpose without the loss of each group’s or individual’s uniqueness. (e pluribus unum.) In fact, pluralism like this is one of the sine qua nons for a functioning democratic republic and in that sense a significant social good.

While essentially a social good, in practice pluralism presents a number of functional problems when it comes to engaging in productive problem solving and ethical decision making. One of the most significant of these problems, and the focus of this essay, is the problem of finding fundamental or central points of agreement upon which to build a coherent philosophical or political case that will be meaningful to all parties.

Some of the problems of communicating across differing groups are evident and well known.  Communication across differing groups can be limited by differences in language.  Spanish speakers may not understand English speakers and English speakers in turn may not understand French or Russian or  Mandarin speakers.  Interpreters can help but subtle nuances are often lost especially when the speakers use idiomatic language.

In cases where these superficial language barriers are worked through, communication can still remain only partial because of differences in the meanings of words in differing cultures.  For example, while a term like “marriage” in whatever language it is spoken may denote or name the same thing, connotative differences will remain from culture to culture.

For the sake of argument, assume that most, if not all, language and cultural barriers to clear communication could be overcome in the US and that as a consequence, citizens could communicate in a manner that everyone understood and that public debate was therefore carried on in a manner understood by almost everyone.  One road block to enjoying the full benefits of being a pluralistic society would certainly have been removed.

Clear communication would, however, not ensure that those engaged in public debate had similar values or even aims in life.  In addition, people vary in intelligence, articulateness and other important things like capacity for empathy.  Some of this variation would likely be a good thing as those who could now talk clearly with one another learned about others values, abilities, cultures and a multitude of other things.  In the course of this dialogue, some values would likely become more widely shared and even grow in the depth of their meaning.  At the same time, sharp differences in values and life aims would also likely arise.

Shared values and perspectives would bring our society closer together at the same time that sharply differing values and aims would contribute to lack of agreement and some degree of social fragmentation.   We would come to agree on the things we could agree on and continue to dispute those issues upon which we could not agree.  If decisions needed to be made on disputed issues, we would, and do, turn to the ballot box or the courts to settle a dispute for the moment.  For example, there remains substantial disagreement around the question of abortion.  The Supreme Court in the Roe v Wade decision determined that citizens have the right to privacy and that the question of whether or not to have an abortion was a private decision between a woman and her medical provider.  Those who do not agree with this decision generally abide by it even as they continue to forcefully articulate their point of view in public debate or the courts.

Differences of this sort are to be expected and they are part of what makes for vital society. Public debate, learning, growing, improving our arguments,  and abandoning misguided notions are all part of a free and vibrant community.  In this country, not everyone will always have his/her way but current social regulations and priorities will at least approximate the outcomes of the national conversation.

There is however one type of difference that provides a pluralistic nation unique difficulties.  Religious and non-believing people can agree in practice on a great deal.  For example, a religious and secular person could probably agree that it is good to be kind and at least less good to be indifferent to others.  However, they are unlikely to ever agree on the existence of a “god” who created the universe, has a personal plan for each of us, defines how we should treat one another (what is right and what is wrong) and yearns for our allegiance and devotion.

The theist/believer takes it on “faith” that this divine entity exists.  The believer believes that when he or she uses the word for “god” in whatever language they speak that they are referring to something that is “real” albeit in a spiritual sense.  Unlike Santa Claus, the Easter Bunny or any of a variety of other mythological beings, “god” is a “real.”  God “exists” maybe not quite like finite things, such as humans or trees, but “god” is “real” and when we refer to god we are not just talking about an idea.

For the secularist/non-theist, references to “god” refer only to an idea that some people have but to which there is no corresponding reality.  For the secularist, there is no actual entity referred to as “god,” and because of that it is literally nonsensical to refer to a “god” as the source or telos of anything.  “God” does not wish anything, create anything or guide anything because he/she/it/they is/are nonexistent in this or any other dimension of reality. “God” is a word without an existing referent.

The atheist or even agnostic and theist have very different first principles that seem to be irreconcilable.  One believes that something exists and starts from there while the other finds no empirical evidence for the existence of an entity named “god” and lacking evidence regards language that speaks about “god” to be speaking about a reality only in the sense that some, if not most, people believe in something for which their is no empirical evidence. For the atheist or agnostic “god” can have no authority because “god” is nonexistent for the former and of indeterminate existence for the latter.

Since there are numerous religious traditions in our pluralistic society there is an accompanying pluralism of “gods.” This godly pluralism further complicates social dialogue by pitting, from the atheist’s point of view, vying nonentities against one another and further obfuscating reality:  yielding  a multiplicity of delusions.

Believers and nonbelievers can, of course, agree that the difference in point of view I describe above is accurate; i.e., one regards “god” as “real” and the other as not “real.”  One regards “god” as having authority while the other regards “god” as having as much authority as any other non existent thing–none. Once this point is reached and if the interlocutors insist on building their arguments from their first principles, no real progress can be achieved.  The interlocutors might be able to reach similar conclusions using completely different methods:  one using what they feel is the inspired word of god and the other deductive reasoning.  We might, for example, agree that killing without justification is wrong in one moment  and in the next, when one party to the discussion concludes that a justification for killing is the commission of the sin of blasphemy, be in utter disagreement:  why execute someone for saying something insulting about something which does not exist!

Attempts have been made especially by the Roman Catholic ethical tradition to deal with this problem of first principles using the concept of the “natural law.”  Ironically, attempts at reconciling Christian Ethical thinking in this way had more to do with illustrating how Christian thought related to the great minds of the ancients like Plato and Aristotle

          Aristole

Aristotle

than establishing a common ground for debate with contemporary nonbelievers.  The ancient Greek thinkers were widely revered in Renaissance Europe and the Church was keen to illustrate how its thought was supported by that of the ancients even those ancients that did not have the benefit of “knowing Jesus.”  What these thinkers of old could see, the Church argued, was the rational order placed into creation by the rational creator; i.e., god.  Reflection on this natural order could reveal a natural law which while only reflective of divine law was fully congruent with it.  As a consequence, they argued, those things contrary to the natural order–which could be easily seen by believer or nonbeliever–were immoral and vice versa.

Tomas Acquinas

The Dominican Friar Thomas Aquinas adapted Aristotle and contributed substantially to the Roman Catholic “natural law” tradition.

The appeal to “natural law” to enable ethical debate between believer and nonbeliever proved quite useful for several hundred years until views of what was clearly the natural order of things began both to diverge and become less clear.  A simple and current example of this divergence is the view of same gender relationships.  For years, both believers and nonbelievers alike thought of same gender relationships as contrary to nature.  Both believers and nonbelievers alike regarded this type of behavior as unnatural and perverse.  Believers had little need to turn to the authority of revelation in the Bible since natural law arguments sufficed.

Gradually, the scientific study of humankind has revealed that same gender orientation is perfectly natural; i.e., gender orientation is a function of the genetic structure of an individual and that approximately 10% of people are same gender oriented. Gender orientation is not a choice nor is it contrary to nature.  Natural law, which once sufficed to arbitrate the morality of same gender sexual behavior, could no longer fully support arguments against same gender relationships in our age.

Believers had to revert to divine authority to bolster their public case.  In practice, they therefor turned  to texts in which believers believe that “god” has revealed his (usually his) divine will.  These texts are taken by believers to be supremely authoritative and literally true.

Nonbelievers, of course,  think that since god does not exist he/she/it/they has/have never said anything.  Belief in these texts as authoritative is therefore as delusional  as the belief in the spiritual entity who is said to have inspired them.  Since “god” does not exist, communications from “god” do not exist either.  While there may be cultural history interest in understanding what the priestly authors of  Leviticus had to say or in what Paul of Tarsus

Famously pictured here by Caravaggio, Paul of Tarus was said to have been directly converted by God on the road to Damascus after which he spread Christianity widely in the Mediterranean Basin.  Called, "The Apostle to the Gentiles."

Famously pictured here by Caravaggio, Paul of Tarus was said to have been directly converted by God on the road to Damascus after which he spread Christianity widely in the Mediterranean Basin. Called, “The Apostle to the Gentiles.”

said about homosexuality, pedophilia or slavery, there is nothing divinely authoritative about these texts if there is no “god” to have shared the divine will with us.

With progress in science and other fields of human study gradually whittling away at the Aristotelian and Catholic natural law tradition almost daily, it is becoming more and more difficult for believers and nonbelievers to find common first principles from which to build compatible ethical frameworks.  If there were no way around this problem, dialogue (at least on first principles) would cease and any sort of rational ethical consensus become much, much harder (if not impossible) to achieve.  “Conversion” of one group to the other group’s position would be the only solution and “pluralism” would be shaken at its roots.

Fortunately, philosophers are a creative lot and have offered a number of “ways-to-think-about-it” that hold some promise for enabling interlocutors who have fundamentally different understandings of reality–like believers and nonbelievers–to not only continue real dialogue but arrive at a point where they agree on a few first principles to which they can both assent.  One example of such a philosopher is the late political and moral philosopher John Rawls.

       John Rawls

John Rawls

 The second part of this essay will explore Rawls’ approach to thinking about justice as a way of illustrating one technique which offers hope for potentially working around the believer/nonbeliever problem; i.e., the thought experiment.

5 thoughts on “Dialogue & Ethical Decision Making in a Pluralistic Society (Part 1)

  1. You write well Tom, What are the facts in regards to debunking the Catholic natural law in regards to homosexuality? You can message me if you like.

    • Thanks for the compliment and the question Sam. Here is a link to a page that explains the RC view of homosexuality. From my knowledge of the subject this is a pretty good summary of the orthodox Catholic view. There are others, on the other side of the question, who argue with scientific data that homosexuality is an in-born (biological) aspect of person and that since it occurs naturally is not a perversion of nature. Here are a few pages that try to summarize the two main scientific schools of thought on the matter–the biological and the sociological .

      Please note that the scientific community tends to see sexual orientation as a complex phenomenon; the etiology of which may be biological, sociological or some combination of both. It was removed from the list of human mental disorders in 1973 and a great deal of research has been conducted since then. Science, of course, always remains open-ended but it does seem that there is a consensus that whether one is homosexual or not is really not a matter of choice and therefore, in and of itself, not really an ethical question.

      As to “debunking” the RC “natural law” idea, what I am saying is that once upon a time what was natural and unnatural seemed pretty apparent to everyone. In those days, it was possible to make an argument against homosexuality as a deviation from the obvious order of nature. As we learned more and more about the nature of nature through scientific inquiry, we also learned that what used to seem obvious might be mistaken. For example, we have learned through physics that the world around us is made up of sub-atomic particles and that some of these particles seem to shift from matter to energy and back again. Facts like these were not obvious to anyone even 20 years ago. What that means is that appealing to a standard like “obviously natural or unnatural” has lost a great deal of its ethical force because we have learned that the nature of nature is not all that obvious to begin with. How obvious is the Higgs Boson, for example? For natural law to function as a middle ground between believers and nonbelievers those two groups would have to have some agreement about the nature of nature and just how obvious that nature was. What this means is that natural law theory has not been “debunked” only that it has become less and less clear as we learn the limitations of what we currently know with certainty about the nature of nature. Once upon a time the Church argued that since we could all obviously see that the natural purpose of sex was procreation then sex without that possibility was unnatural and thus wrong. But if we call into question our knowledge of the nature of nature from a scientific point of view, then we become less able to say that anything is obviously or even logically unnatural.

      In ethical terms this leaves us with two remaining standards for believers and only one for nonbelievers. Believers can be consequentialists or voluntarists. Consequentialism is evaluation of the rightness or wrongness of something based on the consequences of the act. (This is sometime called the teleological approach.) Voluntarism is the view that something is right or wrong because it does or does conform to the divine “will.” Nonbelievers are stuck with consequentialism of some sort because they do not think that there is a “divine will” to violate.

      All this has complicated the landscape of debate between believers (Protestant or Catholic) and nonbelievers (atheist or agnostic).

      So, I want to be clear: I am not saying that science has proved that homosexuality is as natural as any other type of sexuality. It has not, although it has strongly suggested it. What I am saying is that since the mechanics of the workings of nature have become less “obvious,” appeal to natural law as a means of finding a middle ground between believers and nonbelievers has become much less useful and that if we want to continue to have a way for believers and non believers to talk to one another in our pluralistic society we need to find a better means of enabling that dialogue than the “natural law.” In the second part of this essay, I will try to offer the approach taken by John Rawls to defining justice as an example of how this might be done.

  2. Just had time to read part I. I follow the natural law premise and that further knowledge has created a much less obvious common ground. Eager to read a potential way to form new intersections and paths to practical ideas for society. I do wonder if our divergent groups want to find paths to agreement on anything!

  3. I understand the implication that arguing on the basis of natural law is pointless since scientifically there is enough evidence to question the origins of a person’s sexuality. I question whether or not the science community has the two factors correct.
    I notice that the scientific community considers biological and sociological to be predetermining factors in regards to this issue, but interestingly enough leaves choice completely out of the equation. I do not disagree with the scientific community, but I debate the point that choice should not be included as a factor. Predetermined factors undoubtedly affect our lives and the people we are, but choice directs our path. I believe our paths our formed by action, which are constituted by choice, which is influenced by predetermined factors.
    Our founding fathers founded this country with the intent of protecting the free-will of men and women and founded their principals on sound rocks of reason and logic. From my perspective if this is the stance the scientific world takes, then they are just as close minded as the people they accuse of being close minded. Maybe, both sides are right on some points, but since many people fight the wrong battles instead of searching for understanding and truth, we all lose. I view such thinking as a threat to the founding principles of this country. I object to this logic.

    Sam Marcello

  4. Found this through google+ (yes, it is useful) As I read it I was reminded of the response Rt. Rev Gene Robinson has to the question about how he deals with people who use the Bible as the source of the idea that homosexuality is a sin. Gene’s answer paraphrased, “Before we can talk, first we have to agree on what the Bible is, and that agreement we don’t have.”

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s